Episodes
-
On Spinoza's Ethics, Third Part, "Concerning the Origin and Nature of the Emotions."
We want to see how emotions ground ethics, but first, we have to explain what emotions are, which means explaining how mind and body (and causality) work together on Spinoza's account. A passion is being affected by something that we don't understand, whereas reason (which will yield ethical behavior) involves grasping a cause clearly and distinctly. The latter means it's in your individual mind, whereas even if you don't understand the cause, it's still in God's mind, which each of us is essentially a part of.
Read along with us, starting on p. 83 (PDF p. 129).
You can choose to watch this on video.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On "Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values" (1916), Ch. 6 "Formalism and Person," sec. 3, "Person and Act."
While you may want to listen to part one, we're more or less starting fresh, as parts one and two (the latter only available to paying supporters at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy), were mostly about how Scheler rejects Kant's idea of the transcendental ego. We're skipping several pages here to start with section 3 on the recommendation from a member of the International Scheler society, hoping that at least we will find out what makes a person: What makes each of us unique and worthy of moral respect?
Read along with us, starting on p. 382 (PDF p. 415).
You can choose to watch this on video.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
Missing episodes?
-
We discuss "On the Problem of Empathy," ch. 4 "Empathy as the Comprehension of Mental Persons," starting with section 2, "The Mental Subject" and into section 3, "The Constitution of the Person in Emotional Experiences."
We're trying to figure out what these early 20th century German phenomenologists think a "person" is as someone we're able to empathize or sympathize with and which is morally worthy of respect. Stein does this by saying what the "I" (the self) is. It is the thing that "has" experiences, but also something that we understand in terms of a network of motivations, which are different than mere causes, in that they're supposed to be rational. Our self gains definition, Stein says, when we have emotional experiences, which can of course be shallow and undirected (mere moods) or can be very deep and self-revelatory.
Read along with us, starting on p. 87 (PDF p. 107).
You can choose to watch this on video.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On Ch. 6 "Formalism and Person," in Max Scheler's most famous work, Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values (1916). Ethical Formalism is Kant: What makes something ethically correct is just something about the type of act and willing involved. Non-formalism pays attention to the content, e.g. our sentiments (a la Hume).
As we've been studying on The Partially Examined Life, phenomenologists starting with Brentano sought to merge the two: Things in our experience just present themselves as intuitively praiseworthy, and this is sufficient to establish ethical obligations. We have been reading about how Scheler relies in his ethical theorizing on our experiences of sympathy and love, but we wanted to learn more about what it is about particular people that we love and respect: What is it to be a "person" in the moral sense?
This book moves very slowly, so in this part he's still just distinguishing himself from Kant when it comes to saying some basic things about your relation to your own selfhood.
Read along with us, starting on p. 370 (PDF p. 403).
You can choose to watch this on video.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On The Basis of Morality (1840), Part III: "The Founding of Ethics," Ch. 5: "Statement and Proof of the Only True Moral Incentive."
Everything up to this point in the book has been negative: Morality can't be founded on pure reason as Kant thinks, or on the idea of the good life (eudaimonia) per Aristotle. Schopenhauer tells us that all actions are motivated by someone's "weal" or "woe." We are naturally self-interested (motivated by own own weal and woe), but such actions will not be moral. So Schopenhauer's puzzle is: How can I be effectively motivated by someone else's weal and woe? I must somehow identify with that person so that the Other's suffering induces my compassion. This is the only source of moral value.
Read along with us, starting on p. 165 (PDF p. 193).
You can choose to watch this on video.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On Edmund Husserl’s Ideas, Vol. 2 (1928), Section 3, “The Constitution of the Spiritual World,” Ch. 1, “Opposition Between the Naturalistic and Personalistic Worlds."
Given Husserl’s method of “reduction” whereby he sets aside the metaphysical status of objects in the natural world (are they mind-independent or merely ideas?), we wanted to see how he accounts for our ability to directly perceive other people’s minds. We don’t just perceive their bodies and our own bodies and deduce that others must be like us, but we perceive both our minds and those of others as strata (aspects) of physical bodies.
Read along with us, starting on p. 183 (PDF p. 101).
You can choose to watch this unedited on video.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
Mark and Wes read through and discuss the beginning of Felix Guattari's "Everybody Wants to Be a Fascist" (1973). Guattari was a Lacanian psychotherapist, and he argues for explaining fascist tendencies via a "micropolitics of desire," i.e. looking at the individual psychology of fascism instead of merely focusing on sociological, material causes of the rise of fascism.
Read along with us.
You can choose to watch this on video.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
Mark and Wes read through and discuss Karl Marx's "The German Ideology" (1846), delving deep into the middle of his critique of Max Stirner's "The Ego and Its Own" (recently covered on The Partially Examined Life ep. 358). Marx articulates and criticizes Stirner's attempt to distinguish the mere common egoism of an unthinking person from the enlightened egoism that Stirner is recommending.
Read along with us, starting on p. 259 (PDF p. 255).
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
Mark and Wes read through and discuss Edmund Husserl's Ideas (1913), ch. 1, "Matter of Fact and Essence" in First Book, "General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology," Part One, "Essence and Eidetic Cognition."
This is the book that basically designed phenomenology as a movement, and this part of the reading lays some groundwork by describing what these "essences" that phenomenology studies are, and how they differ from matters of fact.
Read along with us, starting on p. 5 (PDF p. 14).
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We're discussing John Stuart Mill's A System of Logic (1843), specifically from Book III, "Of Induction," ch. 8, "Of the Four Methods of Experimental Inquiry." What is induction, and why is it part of logic? Science doesn't just observe regularities, but tries to isolate what is connected with what through a combination of experiments and observations.
Read along with us, starting on p. 278, i.e. PDF p. 284.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We continue reading Part One of Being and Nothingness, with ch. 2, "Negations." We get some context and then jump into the classic question of whether existence in itself is just pure being, such that nothingness is just a result of human judgments on it, or whether nothingness is something objective that we grasp. We end by introducing the famous "absent Pierre in the café" example.
Read along with us, starting on p. 36, i.e. PDF p. 87.
To get future parts, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We skip the introduction of Being and Nothingness (1943) and start with Part One, "The Problem of Nothingness," Ch. 1, "The Origin of Negation."
Read along with us, starting on p. 33, i.e. PDF p. 84.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We begin Bradley's argument for idealism: The world as we perceive it is appearance, not reality. In ch. 1, "Primary and Secondary Qualities," we see him give Locke's arguments for the distinction and Berkeley's response that both alike are in the mind, not the world.
We try to make sense of this given our recent reading for The Partially Examined Life of Thomas Reid, who argued for realism against Berkeley and others.
Read along with us, starting on p. 17.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
Bradley was a prominent British Hegelian, best known now for being the springboard for Bertrand Russell, who was initially a follower but then rejected idealism entirely to co-create what is now known as analytic philosophy. Today we read just the Introduction to this massive 1893 tome, where Bradley argues that metaphysics is possible and worthwhile.
Read along with us, starting on PDF p. 5.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We move from the discussion of the four types of causes, to "disclosure," to an environmental critique.
Read along with us starting on p. 10.
To get parts 3-5, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
What is technology, REALLY? People think of it as neutral, as something that can be used for good or misused, but what is it really to be a TOOL in such a way? Heidegger analyzes causality itself, arguing that our modern emphasis on the mechanical (efficient) cause of something is impoverished as compared to Aristotle's.
Read along with us starting on PDF p. 38: (p. 4 in the text).
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On "The Varieties of Religious Experience," the conclusion of lecture 15. Why do some saintly types engage in ascetic practices like voluntary poverty? James thinks we could all do with some self-discipline of this sort, as extreme as the examples of literary saints may be. Self-denial is a less destructive way of expressing a martial character than actually going to war.
Read along with us, starting on p. 352 (PDF p. 369).
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On "The Intelligence, The Ideas, and Being," starting on section 6. What is "The Intelligence" anyway? How does its storehouse of Forms get into the material world?
Read along with us, starting on p. 51.
To get part 3, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
On "The Intelligence, The Ideas, and Being" from the Enneads (270 C.E.), about the various elements of Neo-Platonist cosmology: You've got The One, which is so awesome that it has literally no properties (so you can't even say it's awesome), then The Intelligence, which is the repository of the Forms (these first two together serve the same function as Aristotle's Unmoved Mover), then The Soul (the World Soul) that actually exists in time and creates things, then lots of little souls, individual Forms that are transmitted around via "the seminal reasons," and the grubby material world that nonetheless may have received enough Form to make us look up the chain of Being toward its divine elements.
Read along with us, starting on p. 46 (PDF p. 48).
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices -
We begin a long series on Maurice Merleau Ponty's "Phenomenology of Perception" (1945), focusing on Part I, "The Body": "Experience and Objective Thought." M-P talks first about what seeing an object (like a house) in the world involves. It pre-supposes a relation to us as perceivers, which involves our situatedness in a body. Yet when we make our own body into an objective object in space and time (like the house), we've shifted it from this primordial center of perception into something described like perception. What is involved in this shift?
Read along with us, starting on p. 77 (PDF p. 102).
To get the subsequent 4 parts of this series, subscribe at patreon.com/closereadsphilosophy.
Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices - Show more